Notes: Ethics: Nature & Scope of Ethics
[This write-up is prepared
primarily on the basis of the IGNOU Study material on Philosophy-Ethics and
certain other materials and is provided here for academic reference for
students. No originality, authorship or copyright to the above is claimed.]
I. Introduction
A. What we Mean by Moral Law?
1. Positive Law
Before
embarking on this question, two things:
Moral
law is called ‘law’ only metaphorically, or if one prefers, analogically.
Primary
meaning of law or positive law is “a rule of action, promulgated by him/her who
is in charge of a community in view of the common good”.
If
the legislator is considered to be God, it is divine positive law; if the legislator is human person, and it is human positive law.
Human
positive law can further be subdivided according to what the common good aimed
at (e.g. civil law, criminal law, commercial law, etc.)
In
a case, a positive law lays down rules to be observed by human persons. It is prescription.
2. Natural Law or Formula Expressing Constant
Behaviour of things
Another
sense of ‘law’: a formula expressing a constant of behaviour of things and of
persons. So we have physical law (including laws studied in physics, chemistry,
biology, etc.), psychological law, sociological law, etc.
(Since
the constant of behaviour among human persons is less fixed and foreseeable
than that among things it is more of a statistical constant).
As
distinct from positive law, this kind of law is called ‘natural law’.
Natural
law is descriptive and also be called prescriptive to the extent if it is
considered as willed by God and includes the divine positive law, and descriptive to the extent that this divine
will is the ultimate cause of the constant of behaviour in things and human
persons.
What then is Moral Law?
However,
moral law corresponds exactly neither to the positive law nor to the natural
law.
On the contrary, the sense of the ‘absolute should’ is an
immediate datum of the moral consciousness itself.
Moral law includes
· general and abstract rules of action (e.g. “do good
and avoid evil”), or, in our language, the sense of the absolute should;
· particular and concrete precepts (e.g. help the
poor, obey legitimate authority, be truthful, do not kill the innocent,
adultery is wrong, etc.). These
particular and concrete precepts, we are here calling the specifications of the
moral law.
B. A Few Questions
Given
the above aspects, following questions arise:
· How are the
general data of the moral consciousness particularized and concretized in
specific precepts and what is the cause of this difference among men?
· In terms of moral
value, if the moral value par excellence is human person’s self-realization as
human how can this moral value determine specific moral values?
· And why is
there disagreement as to whether such and such an action is a ‘good’ (moral
value) or not?
II. Moral Intuitionism
A.
What Is?
All ‘deontological’ theories agree that there
must exist some rule or law which ‘enforces’ moral
value and that it is natural to human person,
intuitively known.
There is then an element of ‘intuition’ in all
of them – no matter how they conceive of it and the way they approach it, whether
as ‘conscience’ (Ockham), ‘Logos’ (Stoics), ‘moral sense’ (Shaftesbury), the
‘a-priori categorical imperative’ (Kant), ‘right reason’ (Thomas Aquinas and
Suarez).
This element of moral ‘intuition’ is also found
in the ‘teleological’ theories whether implicitly or even explicitly:
· It is implicitly found in the
concept of ‘autarxia’ (Epicurus), in that of ‘eudemonia’ (Aristotle), and
· explicitly in the concept of ‘right
reason’ (Hobbes), in the ‘conscientious feelings of mankind’ (Mill).
B.
Prominence of Moral Obligation & Relation with Intuition
The more the idea of moral obligation is
prominent in an ethical theory, the more explicit becomes the recourse to this
element of ‘intuition’ (or ‘direct perception’).
This element of ‘intuition’ is strongly
emphasized by meta-ethicists who maintain that moral language is ‘objective’ and
therefore ‘informative’.
But here again, they differ as to what the
‘object’ of this moral intuition is. This difference is explainable by the
difference in their meta-ethical theories regarding the meaning of moral
‘good.’
Hence for some, this object is the ‘rightness
of specific acts’ (Carritt, Prichard) for others it is a kind of moral
property, simple and indefinable in nonmoral terms (Moore), for others, it is a
general principle (e.g. the ‘the principle of utility’ itself – Sidgwick) or a
set of principles (e.g. the ‘Prima facie’ duties of fidelity, reparation,
gratitude, justice, beneficence, self-improvement and non-maleficence – Ross).
C.
Ethical Intuitionism
In ethics the philosophy which insists on the
necessity of moral intuition is called Ethical
Intuitionism.
But even the most insistent of all moral
philosophers on this element of intuition in the moral consciousness, namely
Kant, not only does not deny, but, on the contrary, explicitly states that
the moral judgment includes elements derived
from experience (which are therefore ‘aposteriori’ as opposed to the ‘a-priori’
element).
Kant denies the possibility of deriving particular
and concrete moral precepts from the concept of practical reason alone. For
this the study of human nature is necessary.
Similarly, Thomas Aquinas distinguishes between
the ‘first principles’ of the synderesis which
are ‘self-evident’, intuitively known by all,
and which cannot be deleted from the human heart,
and the ‘secondary and more specific principles’
which are derived from the former ‘as if by way of conclusion from premises’
what is implied here is that this secondary principles require
reflection.
Thomas speaks of the difficulty involved in
applying general principles to concrete cases. Even though principles whether
theoretical or practical can be evident in themselves, they may not be so
evident to us. And this is due, according to Thomas, to wrong persuasions on
the part of human person.
Saurez is perhaps even more explicit in his doctrine
that even the secondary principles – which
like the primary are self-evident in themselves
– require a certain amount of thought and experience. This is truer of the
tertiary principles which require study and discursive thought.
But all moral principles can be derived from
self-evident principles. One notable difference between Thomas and Saurez is
that the former derives the concrete principles in a way corresponding to ‘human
person’s natural inclinations,’ the latter derives them in a way corresponding
to a legal system.
For Saurez these precepts have their immediate
norm the ‘good’ of human nature. The need of experience and reflection is
similarly – indeed even more insisted upon by contemporary ethicists.
III. Human Person in Search of Himself/
Herself
A.
Ethics & Intuitive Knowledge
The primary question here is whether a general
principle such as ‘serious promises should not be lightly broken’ is
‘self-evident’ and therefore be counted among the ‘first principles’
intuitively known by everybody.
It is possible to argue that there exist first
principles intuitively known by every human. Based on the fundamental precept that a person should realize
himself/herself as human If so, the question would be then which are these
first principles?
If there is any principle that cannot be
denied, it is the immediate data of moral consciousness. If these data cannot
be denied they are self-evident. They are self-evident not as principles, that
is, as formulae but as data whether they are thematically formulated or not.
B.
Human Interrelatedness as the Foundation of Moral Obligation
The immediate ontological foundation of the
moral obligation is human inter-relatedness and that the norm for moral good
(as distinct from the moral right) is human person as a social being.
We have also reflected how the only moral
precept which is immediately given that is self-evident and cannot be justified
on a mere moral level is that human person should be human (as an individual
and social being).
Hence all other precepts (what we are here
calling specifications of the moral law) must somehow or other flow from this fundamental precept that a person should
realize himself/herself as human.
Human consciousness is in a process of
becoming. Human person is becoming moral and more
himself and in the process his awareness of
himself develops. He/she has been continuously asking himself the question what
he is. Human person is in a never-ending search of himself/herself. The more
he/she grows the more he/she becomes conscious of himself/herself as human
person the more he/she is himself/herself.
C.
Moral Consciousness & Moral Precepts
Moral consciousness is a part or an aspect of human
consciousness. The more human person becomes himself/herself the more he/she becomes
conscious of what he/she should be.
This leads to the emergence of moral precepts specifying
evermore clearly the conduct of human person.
Hence the moral
precepts (moral values) flow from the first fundamental moral precept that human
person should be himself/herself (the moral value par excellence not by way of
mere logical deduction or of mere mediate inference.
The former are related to the latter not simply
as logical conclusions or as implicitly correlated to their premises. Logic has
got to do with ideas, with mere ideas. But it is present in the sense that a
continuously developing human consciousness is related to its stages past and
future of its development. Existence is more than logic.
If what we are saying about the progressive
development of human consciousness, and therefore of moral consciousness is
true one can easily understand the development of morals from the cave-man to
modern human person from ancient slavery to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights
which was approved without a dissenting voice in the United Nations General
Assembly in 1948.
D.
Ignorance of Moral Precepts
Ignorance of the moral precepts is a fact of
experience that perverse customs not only weaken the will to pursue the moral
good but darkens the mind to recognize what the moral good is.
But this is more easily possible on an
individual level. Here we are placing ourselves on the level of mankind and its
historical progress. This ignorance and the variety of morals can be explained
by human historicity itself, that is, by the historical progressive development
of his human moral consciousness.
However, we must not easily take it for granted
that this development has always and everywhere been a linear progress. It may
have suffered setbacks, reverses and regress. We need not go into that.
What is more pertinent here to ask is whether
we should reasonably suppose that human person has now attained the some of
his/her self-consciousness and of his/her moral consciousness.
What is reasonable to suppose according to us
is that he/she has not. Apart from the fact that one cannot predict the future,
contemporary moral problem of the morality of abortion hinges to a great extent
on whether one should consider the human foetus a human person.
The so-called women’s liberation movement
indicates no matter what its merits and demerits are that women have not been
treated as full human persons everywhere in the world. One could think of many
other indications. If progress is still possible it can only be done by the passage
of time and on the part of human person by experience and by his reflection on
his own experience.
IV. Love & the Moral Precepts
A.
Love as Existential Basis of Moral Order
To recognize human inter-relatedness as the immediate
ontological foundation of the moral order and to act accordingly can be
expressed in terms of love. Love is therefore the existential basis of the
moral order.
This leads us already to start thinking that
love is the basic moral activity. The primary intuitively grasped demand that
human person realizes himself as a human person is particularized and
concretized in moral precepts. This too can be expressed in terms of love.
Universal
love is particularized and concretized – it is objectified – in the moral
precepts.
Hence as love not just one moral virtue among
others but the form of all of the moral virtues, so too love is not just one
moral precept among others but it is the form of all of them. It is what makes moral
precepts moral precepts. Indeed it could hardly be called a precept since taken
by itself in a non-objectified sense, it does not prescribe anything definite.
B.
Moral Realisation of Oneself
In the same way one can hardly call the moral realization of oneself as human as an
obligation. This too taken by itself in a non-objectified sense does not
oblige human person to do anything specific.
There is hardly any meaning in the saying that
human person should love (love cannot be enforced) so too there is hardly any
meaning in the saying that human person should fulfil himself as human.
If love is the form of the moral precepts and
if love – like human moral consciousness – is a progressive affair this means
that acting according to the moral precepts is acting according to
love but that this awareness admits of degrees.
This means that love can also be considered to be not only the beginning of the
moral life but also its end. At the beginning it is present as a seed – which
is more than mere potentiality but already an actuality albeit in a seminal
form.
The seed can develop into a fully mature and
fully conscious lobe. And if it is in love that human person perfects himself
as human, it is in this fully mature and fully conscious love that he/she does
so.
Many factors go in this process of maturing of
self-fulfilment. No matter how logically we can
distinguish one human faculty (or aspect) of
human person from another human person is a totality one integrated whole. As
it is not the intellect which understands but human person by
his intellect so too it is not with his/her
heart that human person loves but human person by his
heart (but
heart is one’s whole being).
C.
What does Love as Existential Relation Entail?
Love is an existential relation involving my
whole existence. Though human person can develop one or other of his/her faculties
independently of the rest (or at least quasi independently) one cannot develop himself/herself
as a human person without developing the core of his/her being namely his/her love.
This is not achieved by mere study and
reflection – although these can be very useful – but by doing. As scholastics
say the operation is the perfection of being.
V. Dynamics of Morality
The Evolutionary nature of human person and of
his human consciousness has long been recognized one way or another. Charles
Darwin gave the theory of evolution a biological basis.
An Evolutionary view of the world and of human
person is today at the basis of a great deal of
scientific philosophical and theological
thinking. The thinking of such human persons as Pierre
Teilhard de Chardin and of Aurobindo comes of
course spontaneously to mind.
Herbert Spencer is perhaps the best known
Evolutionary ethicist. He starts by observing that both human and animal
conduct consists in acts adjusted to ends. The higher we proceed in the scale of
Evolution the easier it becomes for us to obtain evidence of purposeful actions
directed toward the good either of the individual or of the species. This
purposeful activity forms part of the struggle for existence waged between
individual members of the same species or between different species.
But this type of conduct is according to
Spencer an imperfectly evolved conduct. In a perfectly evolved conduct which is
ethical conduct in the proper sense of the word this struggle for existence
will yield place to cooperation and mutual help. Egoism and altruism will be
both transcended. This leads Spencer to distinguish between absolute and
relative ethics.
Absolute ethics is an ideal code of conduct
formulating the behaviour of the completely adapted human person in the
completely evolved society.
Relative ethics is the nearest approximation to this
ideal according to the more or less perfectly evolved society in which human
person happens to find him/her.
Spencer adopts the utilitarian ethical principle. In fact he takes happiness to be the
ultimate end of life and measures the rightness or wrongness of actions by
their conduciveness to this end. From a nascent state when this utilitarian
principle was dependent on non-ethical (e.g. authoritarian) beliefs it
gradually developed to become independent and as suggested by the theory of
evolution, it will continue to evolve and reach an ideal limit.
Happiness however depends on the fulfilment of
some conditions. And these conditions are the
observances of certain principles and rules
which causally determine human welfare.
Spencer acknowledges the existence of moral
intuitions which however are the slowly organized results of experience
received by the race. In other words, an induction from experience handed down from
one generation to the other ends up by becoming an instinctive moral reaction.
Evolution is
moving towards the emergence of the highest form of life. Happiness as
the supreme end of human person is the concomitant and virtue is the condition
for its attainment.
In the preface of the fifth and sixth parts of
his the principles of ethics subsequently withdrawn Spencer confesses that the
theory of Evolution has not provided as much practical guidance as he had
hoped. What is peculiarly Spencer’s is his interpretation of Evolution as a
teleological process (relating to phenomena in terms of the purpose they serve
than the cause) directed towards the establishment of a higher and higher moral
order.
VI. The Constant & the Variable
in Morality
A.
Development of Human Consciousness
Human consciousness has natured and developed.
At the beginning human person was not necessarily conscious of himself/herself
as human as we today are. On an
individual level this progress in human consciousness is a fact of experience.
The child is a human being but as it grows it becomes more and more conscious of
itself as a human being.
We can accept this theory even on the level of
mankind as such to explain how the moral law is particularized and concretized
in specific moral precepts.
Human consciousness involves one’s
consciousness of oneself as an individual and as a social
being. Moral consciousness is an integral part
of human consciousness.
Primitive human (to call him so) must have been
morally conscious – otherwise we are not entitled to call him/her human at all.
So if moral consciousness belongs essentially to human consciousness as such –
and in a univocal and not in an analogical sense – it has been a kind of
constant in all the later stages of man’s evolution.
However, on the accepted theory that the human
and therefore moral consciousness has been developing, the different stages of
this development can be reasonably considered as the variable in human evolution.
B.
Moral Consciousness & Moral Precepts
If we speak of moral consciousness at all –
whether of the primitive human or ours – we must
speak of it as foundation on the human order more
precisely on human inter-relatedness and these data to be in conformity to
human reason and to be conducive to the self-realization of human person as
human.
But human moral consciousness has been evolving.
This change takes different forms some of which are easily understandable and
afford no real problem to ethics some are not so easily understandable and therefore
afford some difficulty.
As human person becomes more and more conscious
of himself as human – as an individual and as a social being – he/she becomes
more conscious of his/her human inter-relatedness and of his/her rights and
duties as a human person. This clearer self-consciousness is obviously concretized
and particularized in specific moral precepts.
Even at one given stage of human moral
consciousness different people living in different human situations (situations
affecting their inter-relatedness) will live a more or less different moral
life. Such human situations can arise out of geographical, climatic and
economic conditions.
C.
Variability
Since moral consciousness has been in fact
intimately linked to and condition by religious consciousness, different
religious beliefs have produced different moral values. And a change in religious
consciousness has often wrought a corresponding change in morality.
The history of religion affords us with many
examples (e.g. human sacrifice, burning of witches, saturnalia, etc.). This
change is primarily and directly in religious consciousness and only
secondarily and indirectly in moral consciousness. It is a change in the
religiously conditioned morality.
However, a change in civil law governing the
mores of the people does not necessarily mean a
change in morality. When a civil law declares
that something is legal it does not mean to say that it is moral.
Civil law as such does not pass a moral
judgment. Legal means allowed as far as the state is concerned. It is not the
business of the state as such to promote the moral beliefs of one section of
its population as against those of another. This is important to remember today
when many countries proclaim themselves to be secular – today when society is
increasingly pluralistic.
D.
Certitude in Moral Matters, Moral Relativity & Ethical Relativism
The variable in morality raises the important
question regarding the kind of certitude we can have in moral matters. What is
believed to be morally right today can be proved to be morally wrong tomorrow
and vice-versa. Given this, can one be absolutely certain of what is morally
right or morally wrong?
In more philosophical terms if human person is
conditioned by his/her existential situation and if human (and moral)
consciousness is always in a process of development and is dependent on
physiological, cultural, social, psychological environmental and other factors,
can he/she ever be certain of having reached objective moral truth if there is such
a thing as moral truth?
At the very outset, we have to distinguish
carefully between moral relativity
and ethical relativism.
Moral relativity is simply the view that different
people especially in different civilizations and cultures have or have had
different moral beliefs and what is believed to be morally right at a given
time or place may be believed to be morally wrong at a different time or place.
This is an undeniable empirical fact.
But ethical
relativism is the philosophical theory that no foundation exists, there is
no universal moral norm (or basic moral principle), but what is morally right
is relative to the individual or group of men in question.
If such a theory can give reasons for such a
position (as Sartre does), it is ethical relativism in the strict sense. If it
cannot give reasons but simply admits that it is strictly impossible to say
what is morally right and morally wrong it can be reasonably called ethical skepticism.
E.
Dynamic Nature of Knowledge & Morals
In an evolutionary view of human being, that
is, on the accepted theory that human consciousness of himself/herself is
increasingly developing, can we pretend to say the last word
on what human person is? Obviously not.
Human person’s knowledge of his/her self is a progressive
and dynamic knowledge, always tending towards a better and better
understanding. In this sense human person’s knowledge of himself/herself is
relative. And if this is true his/her moral knowledge is also relative in so
far as it is progressive and far from complete.
However, an attentive study of the evolution of
human person’s self-consciousness and of moral knowledge helps one discover a
certain constant progression, that is, human person is becoming more and more
himself/herself.
He/she is becoming more and more conscious of
what he/she really is. His/her moral knowledge helps him/her to recognize
himself/herself and others more and more as persons.
Like in all spheres of knowledge a time of
questioning debate and temporary disagreement is necessary in moral knowledge
if progress is to be made. Indeed a state of incertitude on some issues is a
pre-requisite and the pre-supposition of every progress. But whatever has been
achieved is a definite acquisition – even if this acquisition remains still open
to further advance and a deeper understanding.
Comments
Post a Comment