Notes: Nature of Deductive Logic, Inductive Reasoning & Types of Syllogisms
[This notes is prepared primarily on the basis of the IGNOU Study material on Philosophy-Logic and certain other materials. These notes are provided here for academic reference for students. No originality, authorship or copyright to the above is being claimed.]
Strawson’s Analysis of Nature of Deductive Logic
PF Strawson’s three aspects of formal logic:
1. Generality:
2. Form; and
3. System
· Generality means that individual is
not the subject of formal logic.
· Formal Logic concerns only the
relation between systems but not objects.
Futile to
embark on study involving objects as such a study has no end. e.g.:
Arg. 6:
P1: The author of Abhijnana Sakuntala was in
the court of King Bhoja
P2: Kalidasa is the author of Abhijnana
Sakuntala
Q: Therefore, Kalidasa was in the court of
King Bhoja
Arg. 7:
P1: The author of Monadology was in the court
of the queen of Prussia
P2: Leibniz is the uthor of Monadology
Q: Therefore, Leibniz was in the court of
the queen of Prussia.
Comparison
of Arg 6 and 7 shows both are identical in form and only different in subject
matter. Possible to construct countless such Arg.
Essence of
formal logic is in stating p1 & p2 imply/ entail q or q follows from p1
& p2
What is relevant is the implication/
entailment, which is independent of subject-matter. Without even knowing the
subject matter of p1 and p2, validity of arguments can be determined.
Arg. 7a:
P1: The
author of x was in the court of Z
P2: Y
is the author of X
Q: Therefore,
y was in the court of Z.
Logical Forms
Arg. 7a is a logical form. It has two
components:
· Variables: x, y & z
· Consonants: In categorical propositions, words
all, some, no and not are constants
Structure of an argument is determined by
consonants & not variables. Some points on the dependence of the laws of an
argument on consonants:
· Every class of arguments have
definite constants
· Structure of one class of arguments
is different from another class of such arguments
· When the structure of an argument
differs from that of another, the corresponding laws also differ from another.
· See, birds and aquatic creatures
example reg. anatomical features
Integration of Rules
· Structure of argument and rules are
mutually interdependent.
· If it is possible to decide the
structure of an argument and the different classes of argument, it is possible
to achieve formalization/ systematization.
· Formalisation: Enables make a complete set of
rules and classify them so as to correlate with different arguments.
Induction
Induction is a non-demonstrative argument where
the premises are not and cannot constitute conclusive evidences of the
argument.
Induction: Epogage (Aristotle) or Ampliative
(CS Pierce): Conclusion goes beyond the premises.
Experience:
· Provides reasonable grounds for
believing and not conclusive evidence. Inductive experience has sense
experience.
· Therefore, premises are called as
observation-statements.
· Conclusion is not an
observation-statement as it overshoots the material provided by
observation-statements
· e.g., no matter how many crows have
been observed, it cannot be concluded: “All crows are black”.
Whether Inductive Arguments Always Produce Universal
Statements?
· Misconception that inductive arguments
produce universal statements.
· It provides a statement which
depends on experience for further verification but in itself is not an
experience statement.
· At times, experience vouches for the
conclusion
· Inductive leap or generlisation: Leap from observed to unobserved
or unobservable.
· All generalisations are not
universal statements- possible to construct a universal statement without
generalization: e.g., after having looked at all the books in a library, it is
possible to conclude that all books in the library are hard bound,
Inductive Arguments need not be Future Oriented
· Need not be future oriented. Can
also be past-oriented: e.g., history, anthropology and geology.
· Prime characteristics of induction
are :
o
the
conclusion does not necessarily follow the premises, and
o
experience
precedes inference> induction is a posteriori
· Whatever knowledge is acquired after
experience is called a posteriori.
Uncertainty, Probability and Inductive Arguments
· Karl Popper questioned how inductive
logic can be called empirical.
· Inductive arguments called in
philosophy of science as Probability
· Inductive conclusions are only
probable: probability is a matter of degree while validity is not.
· Therefore, inductive arguments can
be less or highly probable.
Deductive Reasoning & Syllogism
When people reason, they use logical pattern as
undercurrents. Logicians tend to discover these undercurrents. They have
standard form arguments and compares them with arguments.
Logicians generalize argument types>
important for deduction, without which it will be merely rhetoric without
practical value.
Comparison of Lay-Man & Logicians Words
Arg.1
Lay-man’s method: ‘Does God exist? Of course, he does not! No one
has ever seen him, heard him, talked to him; has any one?’
Logician’s Method:
All bodies which exist are
perceivable. BAP
God is not perceivable. GEP
∴ God is not a body which exists. ∴GEB
Arg.2
Lay-man’s method: ‘Was the
Neanderthal a man? Yes he was. In fact we have proof to assert that he made
tools, could paint, lived in groups etc.’
Logician’s method:
All beings who make tools, can
paint, live in groups, etc. are men. BAM
The Neanderthal was a being who
made tools, could paint, lived in groups, etc. NAB
∴The Neanderthal was a man. ∴
NAM
Observations:
· Statements to be proved: Conclusion
· Reasons: Premises
· Order is immaterial but conclusions
generally appear in the end and are preceded by therefore, as a result,
consequently, etc.
· If conclusion appears at the
beginning, these are preceded with because, for, etc.
· At least one of the premises is a
universal proposition: if not , the syllogism is not valid.
· Only three terms with each term
occurring twice.
·
S
and P of the conclusion are minor (S) and major terms (P).
· The premise in
which the minor occurs is called the minor premise and the premise in
which the major occurs is called the major premise.
· One term is
common to both the premises. This is called the middle term (M).
· In the first example
‘God’ is minor , ‘bodies which exist’ is major and ‘perceivable’ is middle and
in the second example ‘Neanderthal’ is minor, ‘man’ is major and ‘beings
who…groups’ is middle.
Mediate Inference
Again,
order of premises does not matter though, generally, major finds the first
place. Aristotle had convincing reason to choose these names. While the major
has maximum extension, minor has minimum extension. The middle is so called
because its extension varies between the limits set by the minor and the major.
Aristotle argued that our inference proceeds from minor to major through
middle. This explains the meaning of mediate inference.
Types of Syllogisms
Classification
of syllogisms is based on constants: all ,some, not. They are not dependent on
variables. Take the example:
All
X are Y
All
Y are Z
All
X are Z
|
Even
if you replace X, Y & Z by say, P, Q, R or A, B, C, the validity is
unchanged.
|
No X are Y
All
Y are Z
All are Z
|
But
if consonants are changed, it might, but will not necessarily, affect logical
validity. In this illustration, consonant in the major premise is changed
alters the logical validity even though the variables are the same: the
syllogism is invalid.
|
Some
X are Y
All
Y are Z
Some
X are Z
|
This
is an example of a case where change of consonants results in logical
validity. In this illustration, consonant in the major premise is changed
alters the logical validity even though the variables are the same: the syllogism
is invalid.
|
Therefore, the logical status, that is, validity/ invalidity
is not determined by the variables but by the consonants.
Simple, General & Compound Propositions in Logic
English
sentences are either true or false or neither. Consider the following
sentences:
1.
Warsaw is the capital of Poland.
2.
2 + 5 = 3.
3.
How are you?
The
first sentence is true, the second is false, while the last one is neither true
nor false.
A
statement that is either true or false but not both is called a proposition.
Propositional
logic deals with such statements and compound propositions that combine
together simple propositions (e.g., combining sentences (1) and (2) above we
may say “Warsaw is the capital of Poland and 2+5 = 3”).
Several
propositions are compounded using constants. Each constant determines the
species which belongs to the sub-class.
Conditional Proposition: A proposition of the form “if p
then q” or “p implies q”, represented “p ! q”
is called a conditional proposition. For instance: “if John is from
Chicago then John is from Illinois”.
Three Kinds of Conditional Syllogisms
·
Pure Hypothetical Syllogism
o All
propositions are hypothetical: ‘hypothetical’ because they express a condition
o Words ;if…
then’ constitute the condition and also the constant: if no consonant, then it
ceases to be hypothetical.
o
Statement after ‘if’: antecedent
Statement after
‘then’: consequent
o
One statement is common to two premises.
o
If quality is constant, then it would appear in one
statement as antecedent and in another as constant.
o
Both the premises as well as the conclusion are
conditionals. For such a conditional to
be valid the antecedent of one premise must match the consequent of the
other. What one may validly conclude,
then, is a conditional containing the remaining antecedent as antecedent and
the remaining consequent as consequent..
Affirmative
If A, then B.
If B, then C.
(So) If A,
then C
If this party
wins, then we shall have a good government:
If we shall
have a good government, then we shall prosper:
Therefore, if
this party wins, then we shall prosper:
|
Negative
If A, then
not B
If not B,
then not C.
(So) If A,
then not C
If this party
wins, then we shall not have a good government
If we shall
not have a good government
|
·
Mixed Hypothetical Syllogism
o
If major premise alone is hypothetical. The minor premise
and the conclusion are merely simple or general.
If A then B
A
Therefore, B
|
E.g., If I do
my duty, then I shall be happy
I do my duty
Therefore, I
shall be happy
|
o
Middle Proposition:
§ No middle term
§ But there is
middle proposition common to major and minor premise
o Modus Ponens:
Affirming the Antecedent
§ Modus ponens or
modus ponendo ponens (La- mode that by affirming affirms) is not a logical rule
but a rule of inference.
§ The mechanism
is antique and has been used in Ancient Greece (Theophrastus) and in India
§ Formal
notation:


E.g. If today
is Monday, Ravi will go to work
Today is Monday
Therefore, Ravi
will go to work
Note that the
above argument is valid but may not be true in all cases. For the argument to
be true, the premises must be true.
o Modus Tollens:
Denying the Consequent
§ Modus tollendo
tollens (La-mode that by denying denies) or modus tollens is an argument form
§ This is an
application of the general form that if a statement is true its contrapositive
would also be true.
§ Eg.: If the
watchdog detects an intruder, it will bark
The watchdog
did not bark
Therefore, the
watchdog did not detect an intruder
o
Fallacies
§ Fallacy of Affirming
the Consequent (AC)
If p, then q.
q.
p.
E.g., If the
watchdog detects an intruder, it will bark
The watchdog
barked
Therefore, the
watchdog detected an intruder
§ Fallacy of
Denying the Antecedent
§ If p, then q.
Not p.
Not q.
§ If the watchdog
detects an intruder, it will bark
The watchdog
did not detect an intruder
Therefore, the
watchdog will not bark
Table:
Valid Forms
|
AA:
Affirming the Antecedent
|
Modus
Pollens
|
If p, then q.
p.
q
|
If today is
Monday, Ravi will go to work
Today is
Monday
Therefore,
Ravi will go to work
|
DC:
Denying the Consequent
|
Modus
Tollens
|
If p, then q.
Not q.
Not p
|
If today is
Monday, Ravi will go to work
Ravi will not
go to work
Therefore,
today is not Monday
|
|
Invalid Forms
|
AC:
Affirming the Consequent
|
Fallacy
of Affirming the Consequent
|
If p, then q.
q.
p.
|
If today is
Monday, Ravi will go to work
Ravi will go
to work
Therefore, Today is Monday
|
DA:
Denying the Antecedent
|
Fallacy
of Denying the Antecedent
|
If p, then q.
Not p.
Not q.
|
If today is
Monday, Ravi will go to work
Today is not
Monday
Therefore, Ravi will not go to work
|
·
Disjunctive Syllogism
o
The components of a disjunctive proposition--p and q--are
called disjuncts. Such a statement does not actually assert that p is true, or
that q is, but it does say that one or the other of them is true.
o
Logical Form:
Either
p or q.
p.
Therefore,
Not-q.
|
Either
p or q.
q.
Therefore,
Not-p.
|
o
E.g.,
Either the
meeting is in room 302, or it is in room 306.
It is not in
room 302.
Therefore, it
is in room 306.
o
So long as we eliminate all the disjuncts but one, that one
must be true--assuming, of course, that the disjunctive premise is true to
begin with.
o Inclusive &
Exclusive ‘or’
§ The disjunctive
syllogism proceeds by denying one of the disjuncts.
§ Is it equally
valid to argue by affirming a disjunct? Is the following inference valid? The
answer depends on how we are using the conjunction "or."
§ Exclusive Sense: We sometimes
use it in what is called the exclusive sense to mean, "p or q but not
both," as in, "Tom is either asleep or reading."
§ An argument
that denies a disjunct is valid in either case, but an argument that affirms a
disjunct is valid only if "or" is used in the exclusive sense.
§ Inclusive Sense: We also use
"or" in the inclusive sense to mean, "p or q or both," as
in, "If she's tired or busy, she won't call back."
§ The problem is
that nothing in the logical form of the argument tells us which sense is being
used. To make it clear that p and q are exclusive alternatives, people
sometimes say, "p, or else q."
§ But, in most
cases, we have to decide from the context which sense is intended.
§ For logical
purposes, therefore, we assume that "or" is used inclusively, so that
affirming a disjunct is fallacious.
§ In cases where
such an argument seems valid intuitively, it is easy to translate the argument
into a different form that makes the validity clear.
Comments
Post a Comment