Notes: Nature of Deductive Logic, Inductive Reasoning & Types of Syllogisms

[This notes is prepared primarily on the basis of the IGNOU Study material on Philosophy-Logic and certain other materials. These notes are provided here for academic reference for students. No originality, authorship or copyright to the above is being claimed.]

Strawson’s Analysis of Nature of Deductive Logic


PF Strawson’s three aspects of formal logic:

1.     Generality:
2.     Form; and
3.     System

·       Generality means that individual is not the subject of formal logic.
·       Formal Logic concerns only the relation between systems but not objects.

Futile to embark on study involving objects as such a study has no end. e.g.:

Arg. 6:
P1:       The author of Abhijnana Sakuntala was in the court of King Bhoja
P2:       Kalidasa is the author of Abhijnana Sakuntala
Q:        Therefore, Kalidasa was in the court of King Bhoja

Arg. 7:

P1:       The author of Monadology was in the court of the queen of Prussia
P2:       Leibniz is the uthor of Monadology
Q:        Therefore, Leibniz was in the court of the queen of Prussia.

Comparison of Arg 6 and 7 shows both are identical in form and only different in subject matter. Possible to construct countless such Arg.

Essence of formal logic is in stating p1 & p2 imply/ entail q or q follows from p1 & p2

What is relevant is the implication/ entailment, which is independent of subject-matter. Without even knowing the subject matter of p1 and p2, validity of arguments can be determined.

Arg. 7a:

P1:       The author of x was in the court of Z
P2:       Y is the author of X
Q:        Therefore, y was in the court of Z.

Logical Forms


Arg. 7a is a logical form. It has two components:

·       Variables: x, y & z
·       Consonants: In categorical propositions, words all, some, no and not are constants

Structure of an argument is determined by consonants & not variables. Some points on the dependence of the laws of an argument on consonants:

·       Every class of arguments have definite constants
·       Structure of one class of arguments is different from another class of such arguments
·       When the structure of an argument differs from that of another, the corresponding laws also differ from another.
·       See, birds and aquatic creatures example reg. anatomical features

Integration of Rules


·       Structure of argument and rules are mutually interdependent.
·       If it is possible to decide the structure of an argument and the different classes of argument, it is possible to achieve formalization/ systematization.
·       Formalisation: Enables make a complete set of rules and classify them so as to correlate with different arguments.

Induction


Induction is a non-demonstrative argument where the premises are not and cannot constitute conclusive evidences of the argument.

Induction: Epogage (Aristotle) or Ampliative (CS Pierce): Conclusion goes beyond the premises.

Experience:
·       Provides reasonable grounds for believing and not conclusive evidence. Inductive experience has sense experience.
·       Therefore, premises are called as observation-statements.
·       Conclusion is not an observation-statement as it overshoots the material provided by observation-statements
·       e.g., no matter how many crows have been observed, it cannot be concluded: “All crows are black”.

Whether Inductive Arguments Always Produce Universal Statements?


·       Misconception that inductive arguments produce universal statements.
·       It provides a statement which depends on experience for further verification but in itself is not an experience statement.
·       At times, experience vouches for the conclusion
·       Inductive leap or generlisation: Leap from observed to unobserved or unobservable.
·       All generalisations are not universal statements- possible to construct a universal statement without generalization: e.g., after having looked at all the books in a library, it is possible to conclude that all books in the library are hard bound,

Inductive Arguments need not be Future Oriented


·       Need not be future oriented. Can also be past-oriented: e.g., history, anthropology and geology.
·       Prime characteristics of induction are :
o   the conclusion does not necessarily follow the premises, and
o   experience precedes inference> induction is a posteriori

·       Whatever knowledge is acquired after experience is called a posteriori.

Uncertainty, Probability and Inductive Arguments


·       Karl Popper questioned how inductive logic can be called empirical.
·       Inductive arguments called in philosophy of science as Probability
·       Inductive conclusions are only probable: probability is a matter of degree while validity is not.
·       Therefore, inductive arguments can be less or highly probable.


Deductive Reasoning & Syllogism


When people reason, they use logical pattern as undercurrents. Logicians tend to discover these undercurrents. They have standard form arguments and compares them with arguments.

Logicians generalize argument types> important for deduction, without which it will be merely rhetoric without practical value.

Comparison of Lay-Man & Logicians Words


Arg.1


Lay-man’s method: ‘Does God exist? Of course, he does not! No one has ever seen him, heard him, talked to him; has any one?’

Logician’s Method:
All bodies which exist are perceivable.          BAP
God is not perceivable.                                   GEP
God is not a body which exists.                  GEB

Arg.2


Lay-man’s method: ‘Was the Neanderthal a man? Yes he was. In fact we have proof to assert that he made tools, could paint, lived in groups etc.’

Logician’s method:

All beings who make tools, can paint, live in groups, etc. are men.                          BAM
The Neanderthal was a being who made tools, could paint, lived in groups, etc.     NAB
The Neanderthal was a man.                                                                                    NAM

Observations:
·       Statements to be proved: Conclusion
·       Reasons: Premises
·       Order is immaterial but conclusions generally appear in the end and are preceded by therefore, as a result, consequently, etc.
·       If conclusion appears at the beginning, these are preceded with because, for, etc.
·       At least one of the premises is a universal proposition: if not , the syllogism is not valid.
·       Only three terms with each term occurring twice.
·       S and P of the conclusion are minor (S) and major terms (P).
·       The premise in which the minor occurs is called the minor premise and the premise in which the major occurs is called the major premise.
·       One term is common to both the premises. This is called the middle term (M).
·       In the first example ‘God’ is minor , ‘bodies which exist’ is major and ‘perceivable’ is middle and in the second example ‘Neanderthal’ is minor, ‘man’ is major and ‘beings who…groups’ is middle.

Mediate Inference


Again, order of premises does not matter though, generally, major finds the first place. Aristotle had convincing reason to choose these names. While the major has maximum extension, minor has minimum extension. The middle is so called because its extension varies between the limits set by the minor and the major. Aristotle argued that our inference proceeds from minor to major through middle. This explains the meaning of mediate inference.

Types of Syllogisms


Classification of syllogisms is based on constants: all ,some, not. They are not dependent on variables. Take the example:

All X are Y
All Y are Z
All X are Z
Even if you replace X, Y & Z by say, P, Q, R or A, B, C, the validity is unchanged.
No X are Y
All Y are Z
All  are Z
But if consonants are changed, it might, but will not necessarily, affect logical validity. In this illustration, consonant in the major premise is changed alters the logical validity even though the variables are the same: the syllogism is invalid.
Some X are Y
All Y are Z
Some X are Z
This is an example of a case where change of consonants results in logical validity. In this illustration, consonant in the major premise is changed alters the logical validity even though the variables are the same: the syllogism is invalid.

Therefore, the logical status, that is, validity/ invalidity is not determined by the variables but by the consonants.

Simple, General & Compound Propositions in Logic

English sentences are either true or false or neither. Consider the following sentences:

1. Warsaw is the capital of Poland.
2. 2 + 5 = 3.
3. How are you?

The first sentence is true, the second is false, while the last one is neither true nor false.

A statement that is either true or false but not both is called a proposition.

Propositional logic deals with such statements and compound propositions that combine together simple propositions (e.g., combining sentences (1) and (2) above we may say “Warsaw is the capital of Poland and 2+5 = 3”).

Several propositions are compounded using constants. Each constant determines the species which belongs to the sub-class.

Conditional Proposition: A proposition of the form “if p then q” or “p implies q”, represented “p ! q” is called a conditional proposition. For instance: “if John is from Chicago then John is from Illinois”.

Three Kinds of Conditional Syllogisms

·       Pure Hypothetical Syllogism

o   All propositions are hypothetical: ‘hypothetical’ because they express a condition
o   Words ;if… then’ constitute the condition and also the constant: if no consonant, then it ceases to be hypothetical.
o   Statement after ‘if’: antecedent
Statement after ‘then’: consequent
o   One statement is common to two premises.
o   If quality is constant, then it would appear in one statement as antecedent and in another as constant.
o   Both the premises as well as the conclusion are conditionals.  For such a conditional to be valid the antecedent of one premise must match the consequent of the other.  What one may validly conclude, then, is a conditional containing the remaining antecedent as antecedent and the remaining consequent as consequent..

Affirmative
If A, then B.
If B, then C.
(So) If A, then C

If this party wins, then we shall have a good government:      
If we shall have a good government, then we shall prosper:        
Therefore, if this party wins, then we shall prosper:
Negative
If A, then not B
If not B, then not C.
(So) If A, then not C


If this party wins, then we shall not have a good government
If we shall not have a good government



·       Mixed Hypothetical Syllogism

o   If major premise alone is hypothetical. The minor premise and the conclusion are merely simple or general.

If A then B
A
Therefore, B
E.g., If I do my duty, then I shall be happy
I do my duty
Therefore, I shall be happy



o   Middle Proposition:
§  No middle term
§  But there is middle proposition common to major and minor premise

o   Modus Ponens: Affirming the Antecedent

§  Modus ponens or modus ponendo ponens (La- mode that by affirming affirms) is not a logical rule but  a rule of inference.
§  The mechanism is antique and has been used in Ancient Greece (Theophrastus) and in India
§  Formal notation:  


E.g. If today is Monday, Ravi will go to work
Today is Monday
Therefore, Ravi will go to work

Note that the above argument is valid but may not be true in all cases. For the argument to be true, the premises must be true.

o   Modus Tollens: Denying the Consequent

§  Modus tollendo tollens (La-mode that by denying denies) or modus tollens is an argument form
§  This is an application of the general form that if a statement is true its contrapositive would also be true.
§  Eg.: If the watchdog detects an intruder, it will bark
The watchdog did not bark
Therefore, the watchdog did not detect an intruder

o   Fallacies
§  Fallacy of Affirming the Consequent (AC)
If p, then q.
q.
p.

E.g., If the watchdog detects an intruder, it will bark
The watchdog barked
Therefore, the watchdog detected an intruder

§  Fallacy of Denying the Antecedent
§  If p, then q.
Not p.
Not q.

§  If the watchdog detects an intruder, it will bark
The watchdog did not detect an intruder
Therefore, the watchdog will not bark

Table:
                       
Valid Forms
AA: Affirming the Antecedent
Modus Pollens
If p, then q.
p.
q
If today is Monday, Ravi will go to work
Today is Monday
Therefore, Ravi will go to work

DC: Denying the Consequent
Modus Tollens
If p, then q.
Not q.
Not p
If today is Monday, Ravi will go to work
Ravi will not go to work
Therefore, today is not Monday
Invalid Forms
AC: Affirming the Consequent
Fallacy of Affirming the Consequent
If p, then q.
q.
p.

If today is Monday, Ravi will go to work
Ravi will go to work
Therefore, Today is Monday
DA: Denying the Antecedent
Fallacy of Denying the Antecedent
If p, then q.
Not p.
Not q.

If today is Monday, Ravi will go to work
Today is not Monday
Therefore, Ravi will not go to work

·       Disjunctive Syllogism

o   The components of a disjunctive proposition--p and q--are called disjuncts. Such a statement does not actually assert that p is true, or that q is, but it does say that one or the other of them is true.

o   Logical Form:

Either p or q.
p.
Therefore, Not-q.
Either p or q.
q.
Therefore, Not-p.

o   E.g.,
Either the meeting is in room 302, or it is in room 306.
It is not in room 302.
Therefore, it is in room 306.

o   So long as we eliminate all the disjuncts but one, that one must be true--assuming, of course, that the disjunctive premise is true to begin with.

o   Inclusive & Exclusive ‘or’

§  The disjunctive syllogism proceeds by denying one of the disjuncts.

§  Is it equally valid to argue by affirming a disjunct? Is the following inference valid? The answer depends on how we are using the conjunction "or."

§  Exclusive Sense: We sometimes use it in what is called the exclusive sense to mean, "p or q but not both," as in, "Tom is either asleep or reading."

§  An argument that denies a disjunct is valid in either case, but an argument that affirms a disjunct is valid only if "or" is used in the exclusive sense.

§  Inclusive Sense: We also use "or" in the inclusive sense to mean, "p or q or both," as in, "If she's tired or busy, she won't call back."

§  The problem is that nothing in the logical form of the argument tells us which sense is being used. To make it clear that p and q are exclusive alternatives, people sometimes say, "p, or else q."

§  But, in most cases, we have to decide from the context which sense is intended.

§  For logical purposes, therefore, we assume that "or" is used inclusively, so that affirming a disjunct is fallacious.

§  In cases where such an argument seems valid intuitively, it is easy to translate the argument into a different form that makes the validity clear.



Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Notes: Figure, Mood and the Possible Types of Syllogisms (Part I)

Notes on Vaiseshika

Notes: Logic: Rules of Categorical Syllogisms